What is a function anyway?

by Willie Wong

I tried to teach differential geometry to a biophysicist friend yesterday (at his request; he doesn’t really need to know it, but he wanted to know how certain formulae commonly used in their literature came about). Rather surprisingly I hit an early snag. Hence the title of this entry.

Part of the problem was, as usual, my own folly. Since he is more interested in vector fields and tensor fields, I thought I can take a short cut and introduce notions more with a sheafy flavour. (At the end of the day, tangent and cotangent spaces are defined (rather circularly) as dual of each other, and each with a partial, hand-wavy description.) I certainly didn’t expect having to spend a large amount of time explaining the concept of the function.

Now, don’t get me wrong, my friend knew what a function is. He just doesn’t know what a function really is. Let me explain. I was trying to explain how a vector field can be treated as intrinsic objects, and that its presentation as a ordered list of functions is a consequence of us putting a coordinate system on it, and how a vector field can “look” constant in one coordinate system without being constant in another coordinate system (which I hoped would lead up to a discussion of covariant differentiation). To motivate the discussion and lead off with an example, I started talking about a function as assigning to every point in the plane a real number, and how to visualize it as a height graph over the plane. Simple, right?

“But what is the function?” he asked.

After a bit of back and forth, I finally realized that the difficulty likes in something far, far more devious than I imagined. The problem is that he was perfectly comfortable with thinking in mathematics of the function as a formula, one that inputs several numbers, churns them, and spits out another number. But somehow he didn’t quite grasp the idea that a function can input a geometric object (say a point) and throw out a number.

Thank goodness that he is a bit of a programmer, and after a while he tapped into his knowledge of the C++ functions

“Oh, so you mean a function more like a function in C++, where the argument can be an array, a string, or an object…” he made the connection.

“… or that power button there, or a point on a piece of paper, or an elephant,” I finished his sentence. I added, “A function that returns the decimal representation of the skin colour can certainly take an elephant as an input.”

After thus freeing his mind, the discussion sped up quite a bit (except for when “now a tangent vector at a point takes as input a function defined on the plane and returns the slope in its direction” blew his mind again. Maybe I should try teaching him distribution theory).

So, what is a function any way?

I am inclined to believe that most Americans (for argument sake, I may as well say most Taiwanese youths; the key being a certain level of development in the education system) have learned, or seen in class (unfortunately the two are no longer equal), during sometime between end of elementary school and the first years of high school something of the following descriptions:

  • A function is a sort of black box, a machine. The output it spits out depends on the input you put in. But it is well-determined, in that if put in the same input multiple times, it will always spit out the same output.
  • A function is a mapping or an association between two groups of objects. For each item in the first group it associates one item in the second group. Multiple items in the first group can be linked to the same item in the second group, but not vice versa.
  • A function is a set of arrows among a set of dots. Each dot can only have one arrow coming out of it, but can have multiple arrows going in.
  • … and many more

And many students would have suffered through a New Math type description of this abstract function business, and spent some time describing the domain and range for some impossibly outrageous associations (a map from zoo animals to kitchen furniture, let’s say), and determining whether pictorial representations are in fact functions or not.

And then they hit the class variously called “Analytic Geometry” or “College Algebra” or “Pre-Calculus”, where all functions are now between subsets of the real numbers (every now and then a daring teacher will introduce complex numbers to often disastrous results), and more attention is paid to correctly using interval notation in combination with logical operators (such as [0,1) \vee (3,\infty)) to denote subsets of real number than the actual meaning of those subsets!

And soon the students completely forget what a function actually is, and their heads stuffed with the notion that a function has to be some closed-form expression operating on a real number which one may, at one’s pleasure, abbreviate f(x).

And thus part of mathematics, as students understand it, becomes taxonomy. Imagine their surprise when they find out that there’s no closed-form expression for \int_0^x e^{-s^2}ds; now imagine their relief when they learn that that problem has been solved, and the answer is called erf(x).

Furthermore, mathematical operations become symbol pushing. There’s no geometrical or intuitive understanding of the “functions” they are dealing with. The attention paid to graphing a function in high school classrooms are often just now lip-service, especially since we entered the age of the graphing calculators. After the introduction of functions with multiple arguments (say, the height function over a plane), students cannot directly visualize the graph without the aid of computers.

And coordinate transformations! Much emphasis has been put in textbooks about “reflections over this line” or “translation in this direction” and that. And students are drilled into dumbly accepting that to translate the graph three units in the positive x direction, it suffices to replace x by x-3 in the argument of the function, without really understanding, or questioning, why a “positive translation” requires “adding a negative number”! This would’ve been a perfect time to teach about active and passive transformations, which can lead naturally to understanding covariant and contravariant operations later in life (should the students enter engineering, physics, or even mathematics).

But no, instead the time was spent on doing more meaningless menial drills on mathematical manipulations that 80% of the class will never once need to use in the rest of their lives.

Mathematics has become a chore for schoolchildren, equally despised by the students who don’t see the point of learning all that abstract nonsense and by the teachers who can’t seem to get the students to be motivated.

Why was mathematics part of the general education anyway? In the United States, there had been a strong emphasis on Reading, Writing, and ‘Rithmetic in the past as basic literacy. In an age with life was simple, those were the skills essential in commerce, and hence essential in surviving in a society. For the erudite elite, however, the mathematical education is generally not about figuring of sums. Rather it was about geometry in the style of Euclid. And that was not taught because it was a life skill (even for land surveyors the uses are limited), but because reading Euclid fosters logical, axiomatic thinking.

The original push to bring more advanced mathematics into classrooms is admirable. Mathematics form the modern foundation of science, and allows us to see the world quantitatively, rather than qualitatively. The benefits from having a logical, rational populace is obvious and appealing. However, this type of mathematics are more behind-the-scenes thinking-machinery than anything else. They are skills difficult enough to teach, and even more so to test. Because in some sense the desired skill is, in effect, an ability to process new information, it cannot really be examined or learned by rote.

And in this simplistic view of history, this is where the tragedy occurred. Rather than figuring out a new way of measuring students’ learning of mathematics, the “educators” chose the perversion of the subject. Testable skills became what is taught. Proofs in geometry must be done in two-column format, and without actually fiddling with rulers and compasses; one can only modify the right hand side of the equation, not the left; techniques in calculus (shell method and washer method, anyone?) are drilled to the point that the students can instantly recognize on an exam, by the wording of the problem, which tool or trick to use, while be completely hopeless in applying it to real-life situations. Teachers have to rely on mnemonics (FOIL, for example) to teach basic concepts, and in the process transforming the students to computing machines with no understanding what it is they are doing. (What’s the point of the endless exercises in expanding and factoring polynomials anyway?) And in the process the students’ minds are turned off one by one.

A problem in maths education at the college level is the students’ misuse of definitions. One of the interesting points that Edwards and Ward make in that article is how some students try to understand mathematics in an a posteriori rather than a priori way. I believe that, at least in part, this tendency can be traced to earlier education in mathematics. That the testing culture promotes by rote the learning of bags of tricks and when to apply the tools is precisely an a posteriori conditioning. By seeing the same types of problems multiple times, the students are expected to infer the common feature between the various problems and learn by experience. While this is certainly part of a mathematician’s working habit, it is not all of it. The other half, rigorous logical deductions, is often lacking from such education.

So what can we do about this? I don’t have a complete solution, nor do I know whether my partial solution is even reasonable. But I’d imagine restoring mathematics to what it really is. There is on the one hand the mathematics that supports the development and study of natural sciences in a quantitative manner, and there is the mathematics that teaches logical reasoning skills. The two should be made separate. The former should be consolidated into a general science curriculum, or failing that, be combined with physics. It is awfully silly, in hind sight, that there are two different AP calculus classes and two different AP physics classes. Considering Newton basically invented calculus to solve problems in mechanics, it seems more natural to just have two classes, one on Mechanics and Calculus, and the other on Electromagnetism and Basic Differential Equations. There should be a qualitative track of nature sciences (or natural philosophy more properly) where natural laws are discussed in a way using only elementary arithmetic. In fact, this track could cover much of the more neglected sciences of a high school curriculum: geology, meteorology, earth and environmental sciences, botany, history of science, etc. In a separate track there can be a quantitative discussion of science, starting with a physics course which subsumes the “analytical geometry”/”pre calculus” course mentioned before. Logarithms can be naturally introduced in the chemistry class, and discrete dynamical systems as an exercise in biology.

The latter of the mathematical curriculum could then be quite honest about itself. Freed from the requirement of “applications in real life”, the course can be abstract and logically sound, while at the same time be interesting. A course in logic leading up to the incompleteness theorem, or a class in group theory from the transformation group point of view are both very doable. Knot theory or discrete mathematics contain lots of easily understandable theorems with lots of “Whoa!” factor. My hope is that as these classes will be exempt from standardized testing, and like music or art, allow the teacher and the students more freedom to teach and to learn.

Advertisements